Editor: We
are continuing our conversation on the role of "grit" in educational discourse
with author Ethan Ris’ response to the earlier post by Paul Thomas.
Response to
Paul Thomas
By Ethan Ris
Before I
address Thomas’s critique, a word about where this article came from. This was
a bit of a departure for me, since my primary work is on higher education.
While researching a piece about the social construction of “non-cognitive”
skills in college (recently published in History of Education),
I found myself reading the works of Horatio Alger, Jr., the 19th
century children’s book writer. Digging through his miserable prose, I was
surprised to find an early version of the “grit” discourse that has figured
prominently in pedagogical theory over the last five or so years.
As I explain
in my article, Alger’s books (contrary to popular belief) were written for
middle and upper-class children. They were about
poor children, but not for them. Instead, they used striving street urchins and
farm boys as virtuous exemplars of grit and tenacity. The message to privileged
boys and girls was a simple one: compared
to these kids, you are spoiled – and if you don’t shape up, they will eat your
lunch. That warning was particularly potent in the late 19th
century, a time of increasing income inequality, a burgeoning labor movement,
and the rising specter of socialism.
While I was
struck by the long legs of the grit discourse, I was also struck by how rarely
its co-creators acknowledge its basis in worries about privileged children, a
trend that continued throughout much of the 20th century. I argue
that that oversight is equally true for both those who see grit theory as a
panacea for the ails of low-income students, and for critics who argue that it
is another form of victim-blaming, like cultural deficit theory.
Paul Thomas takes
issue with my equivalency of the proponents and the critics, pointing out that
my data and analysis strongly support the latter (among whom he counts himself)
in their argument that the grit discourse punishes low-income children and students
of color. He writes that there is “a direct relationship between ‘grit’ as a
domain of the privileged and how that has created the context within which many
in the U.S. assume black/brown and poor students lack that quality.” Privileged
classes, he argues, perpetuate grit theory “because they need the wider public
to believe that success is the result of effort (merit) and not the consequence
of privilege.”
Thomas is on
firm ground when he points out that I am reluctant to name grit theory as
racist or even classist. My reason for this reluctance comes from my reading of
the historical record, in which poor children are most frequently exemplars of grit in the eyes of elites.
This is even true for contemporary authors who have fueled the grit frenzy –
Paul Tough, for example, peppers his book How Children Succeed with humanistic
case studies of gritty young people who have overcome the disadvantage of their
poor, minority backgrounds in order to succeed academically. It is a short leap
from Tough’s middle-class readers to the ones who gobbled up Horatio Alger’s
tales of Ragged Dick and Paul the Peddler, seeing in them answers to their
concerns about their own children.
For that
reason, I can’t agree with Thomas’s claim that “‘grit’ is racist and classist
because the narrative speaks to and perpetuates race and class stereotypes that
black/brown and poor people are inherently lazy, deserving their stations in
life.” I don’t believe that Angela Duckworth and other scholars who perpetuate grit
theory directly contribute to that type of prejudice. While they make allusions
to “closing the achievement gap” (which I read as a habitual shibboleth necessary
to get grant funding), their research design indicates their true audience; as
I have pointed out before, Duckworth’s most important samples
are not low-income children but privileged groups like Ivy League
undergraduates and advanced spelling bee contenders. As Daniel Engber writes, studying these high-achieving groups produces classic
“restriction of range” bias, but for my purposes they represent exactly the
types of young people for whom the grit discourse originated.
That said, I
acknowledge and respect Thomas’s point that grit theory easily fits in to a
longstanding racist narrative about the laziness of impoverished people,
especially those of color. (I got a taste of that in the comments on a recent piece I wrote in the Washington Post’s
“Answer Sheet” blog.) While I disagree with critics who allege eugenicist motives for grit research, they are certainly on to
something by highlighting the dangers of “cutting-edge” scientific research
that lends legitimacy to age-old forms of prejudice and oppression. And I am certainly sensitive to Thomas’s
point that a reluctance to call racism by its name makes its eradication that
much more difficult. Let me be clear: grit theory, in the wrong hands, fuels
racism and classism. But I am more concerned about what happens when grit
theory is in the right hands.
My article
concludes on a note of dismay, with a description of how the grit discourse can
harm young people from disadvantaged backgrounds. My study shows that the
historical narrative has poor children serving as role models for privileged
ones. This is different from impugning them as shiftless and unmotivated, but
it is perhaps equally detrimental in its romanticization of hardship and its ploy
of talking about success in terms of character, rather than structural
advantage.
The
difference between my critique of grit theory and Thomas’s critique strikes me
as similar to the two ways to critique the “no excuses” model of schooling. One
focus (with which I am most sympathetic) is on the interpretation of the model
as rejecting macro-level “excuses” like residential segregation, income
disparities, and the legacy of legalized discrimination as reasons for the
academic achievement gap. Obviously, this willful neglect of structural
hardship is troubling. The second set of critics, however, train their fire on the
commonly stated rejection of “excuses” at the student level, which unfairly assumes
that the real problem is that certain types of learners lack work ethic and
blame others for their shortcomings.
Both
critiques are valid, but they pursue two different demons. A similar dichotomy
may be at play here.
This: "And I am certainly sensitive to Thomas’s point that a reluctance to call racism by its name makes its eradication that much more difficult. Let me be clear: grit theory, in the wrong hands, fuels racism and classism. But I am more concerned about what happens when grit theory is in the right hands."
ReplyDeleteI believe you offer the key distinction here that allows us not to focus on "right" or "wrong." Thank you for continuing to tease this out.